De Wikipedia, la enciclopedia libre
Saltar a navegación Saltar a búsqueda

Julian Huxley usó la frase " el eclipse del darwinismo " [a] para describir el estado de cosas anterior a lo que llamó la síntesis moderna , cuando la evolución era ampliamente aceptada en los círculos científicos pero relativamente pocos biólogos creían que la selección natural era su mecanismo principal. [2] [3] Historiadores de la ciencia como Peter J. Bowler han usado la misma frase como etiqueta para el período dentro de la historia del pensamiento evolutivo desde la década de 1880 hasta alrededor de 1920, cuando las alternativas a la selección naturalfueron desarrollados y explorados, ya que muchos biólogos consideraron que la selección natural había sido una suposición errónea por parte de Charles Darwin , o al menos de una importancia relativamente menor. [4] [5] Se ha propuesto un término alternativo, la interfase del darwinismo , para evitar la implicación en gran parte incorrecta de que el eclipse putativo fue precedido por un período de vigorosa investigación darwiniana. [1]

Si bien hubo múltiples explicaciones de la evolución, incluido el vitalismo , el catastrofismo y el estructuralismo a lo largo del siglo XIX, cuatro alternativas principales a la selección natural estaban en juego a principios del siglo XX:

  • La evolución teísta fue la creencia de que Dios guió directamente la evolución. [B]
  • El neolamarckismo fue la idea de que la evolución fue impulsada por la herencia de características adquiridas durante la vida del organismo.
  • La ortogénesis era la creencia de que los organismos se veían afectados por fuerzas internas o leyes del desarrollo que impulsaban la evolución en direcciones particulares.
  • El mutacionismo era la idea de que la evolución era en gran parte el producto de mutaciones que creaban nuevas formas o especies en un solo paso.

La evolución teísta desapareció en gran medida de la literatura científica a fines del siglo XIX cuando las apelaciones directas a causas sobrenaturales se consideraron poco científicas. Las otras alternativas tuvieron seguidores importantes hasta bien entrado el siglo XX; La biología dominante los abandonó en gran medida sólo cuando los desarrollos de la genética los hicieron parecer cada vez más insostenibles, y cuando el desarrollo de la genética de poblaciones y la síntesis moderna demostraron el poder explicativo de la selección natural . Ernst Mayr escribió que aún en 1930 la mayoría de los libros de texto todavía enfatizaban tales mecanismos no darwinianos. [6]

Contexto [ editar ]

La evolución fue ampliamente aceptada en los círculos científicos pocos años después de la publicación de El origen de las especies , pero la aceptación de la selección natural como su mecanismo impulsor fue mucho menor. [7] Se plantearon seis objeciones a la teoría en el siglo XIX: [8]

La combinación de la herencia lleva a promediar todas las características, lo que, como señaló el ingeniero Fleeming Jenkin , hace imposible la evolución por selección natural.
  1. El registro fósil fue discontinuo, lo que sugiere brechas en la evolución. [8]
  2. El físico Lord Kelvin calculó en 1862 que la Tierra se habría enfriado en 100 millones de años o menos desde su formación, muy poco tiempo para la evolución. [c] [8]
  3. Se argumentó que muchas estructuras no eran adaptativas (sin función), por lo que no podrían haber evolucionado bajo la selección natural. [8]
  4. Algunas estructuras parecían haber evolucionado siguiendo un patrón regular, como los ojos de animales no relacionados como el calamar y los mamíferos . [8]
  5. Se argumentó que la selección natural no era creativa, mientras que se admitió que la variación no tenía valor en su mayoría. [8]
  6. El ingeniero Fleeming Jenkin [d] señaló correctamente en 1868, revisando El origen de las especies , que la herencia combinada favorecida por Darwin se opondría a la acción de la selección natural. [e] [8] [10] [11]

Tanto Darwin como su más cercano partidario Thomas Henry Huxley [f] admitieron libremente, también, que la selección podría no ser la explicación completa; Darwin estaba dispuesto a aceptar una medida de lamarckismo, mientras que Huxley se sentía cómodo tanto con el cambio repentino (mutacional) como con la evolución dirigida (ortogenética). [12]

A finales del siglo XIX, la crítica de la selección natural había llegado al punto de que en 1903 el botánico alemán Eberhard Dennert  [ de ] escribió que "ahora estamos en el lecho de muerte del darwinismo", y en 1907 la Universidad de Stanford El entomólogo Vernon Lyman Kellogg , quien apoyó la selección natural, afirmó que "... la verdad es que la teoría de la selección darwiniana, considerada con respecto a su supuesta capacidad de ser una explicación mecánica de la descendencia suficientemente independiente, está hoy seriamente desacreditada en el campo biológico. mundo." [13]Sin embargo, agregó que había problemas que impedían la aceptación generalizada de cualquiera de las alternativas, ya que las mutaciones grandes parecían demasiado infrecuentes y no había evidencia experimental de mecanismos que pudieran respaldar ni el lamarckismo ni la ortogénesis. [14] Ernst Mayr escribió que un estudio de la literatura evolutiva y los libros de texto de biología mostró que hasta 1930 la creencia de que la selección natural era el factor más importante en la evolución era un punto de vista minoritario, con sólo unos pocos genetistas de poblaciones que eran estrictamente selectivos. [6]

Motivación por alternativas [ editar ]

Las alternativas a la evolución por selección natural incluían la evolución dirigida ( ortogénesis ), a veces invocando el control divino directa o indirectamente.

Una variedad de factores diferentes motivaron a las personas a proponer otros mecanismos evolutivos como alternativas a la selección natural , algunos de los cuales datan de antes del Origen de las especies de Darwin . La selección natural, con su énfasis en la muerte y la competencia, no atrajo a algunos naturalistas porque la sentían inmoral y dejaba poco espacio para la teleología o el concepto de progreso en el desarrollo de la vida. [15] [16] Algunos de estos científicos y filósofos, como St. George Jackson Mivart y Charles Lyell , que llegaron a aceptar la evolución pero no les gustaba la selección natural, plantearon objeciones religiosas. [17] Otros, como Herbert Spencer, el botánico George Henslow (hijo del mentor de Darwin, John Stevens Henslow, también botánico), y Samuel Butler , sintieron que la evolución era un proceso inherentemente progresivo que la selección natural por sí sola era insuficiente para explicar. Otros, incluidos los paleontólogos estadounidenses Edward Drinker Cope y Alpheus Hyatt , tenían una perspectiva idealista y sentían que la naturaleza, incluido el desarrollo de la vida, seguía patrones ordenados que la selección natural no podía explicar. [10]

Otro factor fue el surgimiento de una nueva facción de biólogos a fines del siglo XIX, tipificada por los genetistas Hugo DeVries y Thomas Hunt Morgan , que querían reformular la biología como una ciencia de laboratorio experimental. Desconfiaban del trabajo de naturalistas como Darwin y Alfred Russel Wallace , que dependían de observaciones de campo de variación, adaptación y biogeografía , considerándolas demasiado anecdóticas. En cambio, se centraron en temas como fisiología y genética que podrían investigarse fácilmente con experimentos controlados.en el laboratorio, y descartó la selección natural y el grado en que los organismos se adaptaron a su medio ambiente, que no podría ser probado experimentalmente fácilmente. [18]

Teorías anti-darwinistas durante el eclipse [ editar ]

Evolución teísta [ editar ]

Louis Agassiz (aquí en 1870, con dibujos de Radiata ) creía en una secuencia de creaciones en las que la humanidad era el objetivo de un plan divino.

British science developed in the early 19th century on a basis of natural theology which saw the adaptation of fixed species as evidence that they had been specially created to a purposeful divine design. The philosophical concepts of German idealism inspired concepts of an ordered plan of harmonious creation, which Richard Owen reconciled with natural theology as a pattern of homology showing evidence of design. Similarly, Louis Agassiz saw the recapitulation theory as symbolising a pattern of the sequence of creations in which humanity was the goal of a divine plan. In 1844 Vestiges adapted Agassiz's concept into theistic evolutionism. Its anonymous author Robert Chambers proposed a "law" of divinely ordered progressive development, with transmutation of species as an extension of recapitulation theory. This popularised the idea, but it was strongly condemned by the scientific establishment. Agassiz remained forcefully opposed to evolution, and after he moved to America in 1846 his idealist argument from design of orderly development became very influential.[19] In 1858 Owen cautiously proposed that this development could be a real expression of a continuing creative law, but distanced himself from transmutationists. Two years later in his review of Darwin's On the Origin of Species Owen attacked Darwin while at the same time openly supporting evolution,[20] expressing belief in a pattern of transmutation by law-like means. This idealist argument from design was taken up by other naturalists such as George Jackson Mivart, and the Duke of Argyll who rejected natural selection altogether in favor of laws of development that guided evolution down preordained paths.[21]

Many of Darwin's supporters accepted evolution on the basis that it could be reconciled with design. In particular, Asa Gray considered natural selection to be the main mechanism of evolution and sought to reconcile it with natural theology. He proposed that natural selection could be a mechanism in which the problem of evil of suffering produced the greater good of adaptation, but conceded that this had difficulties and suggested that God might influence the variations on which natural selection acted to guide evolution.[22] For Darwin and Thomas Henry Huxley such pervasive supernatural influence was beyond scientific investigation, and George Frederick Wright, an ordained minister who was Gray's colleague in developing theistic evolution, emphasised the need to look for secondary or known causes rather than invoking supernatural explanations: "If we cease to observe this rule there is an end to all science and all sound science."[23]

A secular version of this methodological naturalism was welcomed by a younger generation of scientists who sought to investigate natural causes of organic change, and rejected theistic evolution in science. By 1872 Darwinism in its broader sense of the fact of evolution was accepted as a starting point. Around 1890 only a few older men held onto the idea of design in science, and it had completely disappeared from mainstream scientific discussions by 1900. There was still unease about the implications of natural selection, and those seeking a purpose or direction in evolution turned to neo-Lamarckism or orthogenesis as providing natural explanations.[24]

Neo-Lamarckism[edit]

Jean-Baptiste Lamarck

Jean-Baptiste Lamarck had originally proposed a theory on the transmutation of species that was largely based on a progressive drive toward greater complexity. Lamarck also believed, as did many others at the time, that characteristics acquired during the course of an organism's life could be inherited by the next generation, and he saw this as a secondary evolutionary mechanism that produced adaptation to the environment. Typically, such characteristics included changes caused by the use or disuse of a particular organ. It was this mechanism of evolutionary adaptation through the inheritance of acquired characteristics that much later came to be known as Lamarckism.[25] Although Alfred Russel Wallace completely rejected the concept in favor of natural selection, Charles Darwin always included what he called Effects of the increased Use and Disuse of Parts, as controlled by Natural Selection in On the Origin of Species, giving examples such as large ground feeding birds getting stronger legs through exercise, and weaker wings from not flying until, like the ostrich, they could not fly at all.[26]

Alpheus Spring Packard's 1872 book Mammoth Cave and its Inhabitants used the example of cave beetles (Anophthalmus and Adelops) that had become blind to argue for Lamarckian evolution through inherited disuse of organs.

In the late 19th century the term neo-Lamarckism came to be associated with the position of naturalists who viewed the inheritance of acquired characteristics as the most important evolutionary mechanism. Advocates of this position included the British writer and Darwin critic Samuel Butler, the German biologist Ernst Haeckel, the American paleontologists Edward Drinker Cope and Alpheus Hyatt, and the American entomologist Alpheus Packard. They considered Lamarckism to be more progressive and thus philosophically superior to Darwin's idea of natural selection acting on random variation. Butler and Cope both believed that this allowed organisms to effectively drive their own evolution, since organisms that developed new behaviors would change the patterns of use of their organs and thus kick-start the evolutionary process. In addition, Cope and Haeckel both believed that evolution was a progressive process. The idea of linear progress was an important part of Haeckel's recapitulation theory of evolution, which held that the embryological development of an organism repeats its evolutionary history. Cope and Hyatt looked for, and thought they found, patterns of linear progression in the fossil record.[27][28] Packard argued that the loss of vision in the blind cave insects he studied was best explained through a Lamarckian process of atrophy through disuse combined with inheritance of acquired characteristics.[29] Packard also wrote a book about Lamarck and his writings.[27][30]

Many American proponents of neo-Lamarckism were strongly influenced by Louis Agassiz and a number of them, including Hyatt and Packard, were his students. Agassiz had an idealistic view of nature, connected with natural theology, that emphasized the importance of order and pattern. Agassiz never accepted evolution; his followers did, but they continued his program of searching for orderly patterns in nature, which they considered to be consistent with divine providence, and preferred evolutionary mechanisms like neo-Lamarckism and orthogenesis that would be likely to produce them.[27][30]

In Britain the botanist George Henslow, the son of Darwin's mentor John Stevens Henslow, was an important advocate of neo-Lamarckism. He studied how environmental stress affected the development of plants, and he wrote that the variations induced by such environmental factors could largely explain evolution. The historian of science Peter J. Bowler writes that, as was typical of many 19th century Lamarckians, Henslow did not appear to understand the need to demonstrate that such environmentally induced variations would be inherited by descendants that developed in the absence of the environmental factors that produced them, but merely assumed that they would be.[31]

Polarising the argument: Weismann's germ plasm[edit]

August Weismann's germ plasm theory stated that the hereditary material is confined to the gonads. Somatic cells (of the body) develop afresh in each generation from the germ plasm, so changes to the body acquired during a lifetime cannot affect the next generation, as neo-Lamarckism required.

Critics of neo-Lamarckism pointed out that no one had ever produced solid evidence for the inheritance of acquired characteristics. The experimental work of the German biologist August Weismann resulted in the germ plasm theory of inheritance. This led him to declare that inheritance of acquired characteristics was impossible, since the Weismann barrier would prevent any changes that occurred to the body after birth from being inherited by the next generation. This effectively polarised the argument between the Darwinians and the neo-Lamarckians, as it forced people to choose whether to agree or disagree with Weismann and hence with evolution by natural selection.[32] Despite Weismann's criticism, neo-Lamarckism remained the most popular alternative to natural selection at the end of the 19th century, and would remain the position of some naturalists well into the 20th century.[28][33]

Baldwin effect[edit]

As a consequence of the debate over the viability of neo-Lamarckism, in 1896 James Mark Baldwin, Henry Fairfield Osborne and C. Lloyd Morgan all independently proposed a mechanism where new learned behaviors could cause the evolution of new instincts and physical traits through natural selection without resort to the inheritance of acquired characteristics. They proposed that if individuals in a species benefited from learning a particular new behavior, the ability to learn that behavior could be favored by natural selection, and the end result would be the evolution of new instincts and eventually new physical adaptations. This became known as the Baldwin effect and it has remained a topic of debate and research in evolutionary biology ever since.[34]

Orthogenesis[edit]

Henry Fairfield Osborn's 1918 book Origin and Evolution of Life claimed the evolution of Titanothere horns was an example of an orthogenetic trend in evolution.

Orthogenesis was the theory that life has an innate tendency to change, in a unilinear fashion in a particular direction. The term was popularized by Theodor Eimer, a German zoologist, in his 1898 book On Orthogenesis: And the Impotence of Natural Selection in Species Formation. He had studied the coloration of butterflies, and believed he had discovered non-adaptive features which could not be explained by natural selection. Eimer also believed in Lamarckian inheritance of acquired characteristics, but he felt that internal laws of growth determine which characteristics would be acquired and guided the long term direction of evolution down certain paths.[35]

Orthogenesis had a significant following in the 19th century, its proponents including the Russian biologist Leo S. Berg, and the American paleontologist Henry Fairfield Osborn.[36] Orthogenesis was particularly popular among some paleontologists, who believed that the fossil record showed patterns of gradual and constant unidirectional change. Those who accepted this idea, however, did not necessarily accept that the mechanism driving orthogenesis was teleological (goal-directed). They did believe that orthogenetic trends were non-adaptive; in fact they felt that in some cases they led to developments that were detrimental to the organism, such as the large antlers of the Irish elk that they believed led to the animal's extinction.[35]

Support for orthogenesis began to decline during the modern synthesis in the 1940s, when it became apparent that orthogenesis could not explain the complex branching patterns of evolution revealed by statistical analysis of the fossil record by paleontologists. A few biologists however hung on to the idea of orthogenesis as late as the 1950s, claiming that the processes of macroevolution, the long term trends in evolution, were distinct from the processes of microevolution.[10][11]

Mutationism[edit]

Painting of Hugo de Vries, making a painting of an evening primrose, the plant which had apparently produced new forms by large mutations in his experiments, by Thérèse Schwartze, 1918

Mutationism was the idea that new forms and species arose in a single step as a result of large mutations. It was seen as a much faster alternative to the Darwinian concept of a gradual process of small random variations being acted on by natural selection. It was popular with early geneticists such as Hugo de Vries, who along with Carl Correns helped rediscover Gregor Mendel's laws of inheritance in 1900, William Bateson a British zoologist who switched to genetics, and early in his career, Thomas Hunt Morgan.[37][38]

The 1901 mutation theory of evolution held that species went through periods of rapid mutation, possibly as a result of environmental stress, that could produce multiple mutations, and in some cases completely new species, in a single generation. Its originator was the Dutch botanist Hugo de Vries. De Vries looked for evidence of mutation extensive enough to produce a new species in a single generation and thought he found it with his work breeding the evening primrose of the genus Oenothera, which he started in 1886. The plants that de Vries worked with seemed to be constantly producing new varieties with striking variations in form and color, some of which appeared to be new species because plants of the new generation could only be crossed with one another, not with their parents. DeVries himself allowed a role for natural selection in determining which new species would survive, but some geneticists influenced by his work, including Morgan, felt that natural selection was not necessary at all. De Vries's ideas were influential in the first two decades of the 20th century, as some biologists felt that mutation theory could explain the sudden emergence of new forms in the fossil record; research on Oenothera spread across the world. However, critics including many field naturalists wondered why no other organism seemed to show the same kind of rapid mutation.[39]

Morgan was a supporter of de Vries's mutation theory and was hoping to gather evidence in favor of it when he started working with the fruit fly Drosophila melanogaster in his lab in 1907. However, it was a researcher in that lab, Hermann Joseph Muller, who determined in 1918 that the new varieties de Vries had observed while breeding Oenothera were the result of polyploid hybrids rather than rapid genetic mutation.[40][41] While they were doubtful of the importance of natural selection, the work of geneticists like Morgan, Bateson, de Vries and others from 1900 to 1915 established Mendelian genetics linked to chromosomal inheritance, which validated August Weismann's criticism of neo-Lamarckian evolution by discounting the inheritance of acquired characteristics. The work in Morgan's lab with Drosophila also undermined the concept of orthogenesis by demonstrating the random nature of mutation.[42]

End of the eclipse[edit]

Several major ideas about evolution came together in the population genetics of the early 20th century to form the modern synthesis, including competition for resources, genetic variation, natural selection, and particulate (Mendelian) inheritance. This ended the eclipse of Darwinism.

During the period 1916–1932, the discipline of population genetics developed largely through the work of the geneticists Ronald Fisher, J.B.S. Haldane, and Sewall Wright. Their work recognized that the vast majority of mutations produced small effects that served to increase the genetic variability of a population rather than creating new species in a single step as the mutationists assumed. They were able to produce statistical models of population genetics that included Darwin's concept of natural selection as the driving force of evolution.[43]

Developments in genetics persuaded field naturalists such as Bernhard Rensch and Ernst Mayr to abandon neo-Lamarckian ideas about evolution in the early 1930s.[44] By the late 1930s, Mayr and Theodosius Dobzhansky had synthesized the ideas of population genetics with the knowledge of field naturalists about the amount of genetic diversity in wild populations, and the importance of genetically distinct subpopulations (especially when isolated from one another by geographical barriers) to create the early 20th century modern synthesis.[45] In 1944 George Gaylord Simpson integrated paleontology into the synthesis by statistically analyzing the fossil record to show that it was consistent with the branching non-directional form of evolution predicted by the modern synthesis, and in particular that the linear trends cited by earlier paleontologists in support of Lamarckism and orthogenesis did not stand up to careful analysis.[46] Mayr wrote that by the end of the synthesis natural selection together with chance mechanisms like genetic drift had become the universal explanation for evolutionary change.[6]

Historiography[edit]

The concept of eclipse suggests that Darwinian research paused, implying in turn that there had been a preceding period of vigorously Darwinian activity among biologists. However, historians of science such as Mark Largent have argued that while biologists broadly accepted the extensive evidence for evolution presented in The Origin of Species, there was less enthusiasm for natural selection as a mechanism. Biologists instead looked for alternative explanations more in keeping with their worldviews, which included the beliefs that evolution must be directed and that it constituted a form of progress. Further, the idea of a dark eclipse period was convenient to scientists such as Julian Huxley, who wished to paint the modern synthesis as a bright new achievement, and accordingly to depict the preceding period as dark and confused. Huxley's 1942 book Evolution: The Modern Synthesis therefore, argued Largent, suggested that the so-called modern synthesis began after a long period of eclipse lasting until the 1930s, in which Mendelians, neo-Lamarckians, mutationists, and Weismannians, not to mention experimental embryologists and Haeckelian recapitulationists fought running battles with each other.[1] The idea of an eclipse also allowed Huxley to step aside from what was to him the inconvenient association of evolution with aspects such as social Darwinism, eugenics, imperialism, and militarism.[1] Accounts such as Michael Ruse's very large[1] book Monad to Man[47] ignored, claimed Largent, almost all the early 20th century American evolutionary biologists. Largent has suggested as an alternative to eclipse a biological metaphor, the interphase of Darwinism, interphase being an apparently quiet period in the cycle of cell division and growth.[1]

See also[edit]

  • Coloration evidence for natural selection
  • Objections to evolution

Notes[edit]

  1. ^ In (Huxley 1942, pp. 22–28). Used earlier, c. 1925, in an unpublished manuscript by David Starr Jordan, to imply that Darwinism was in relative decline, the interest of biologists being elsewhere.[1]
  2. ^ This should not be confused with a more recent use of the term theistic evolution, which refers to a theological belief in the compatibility of science and religion.
  3. ^ Years later, the discovery of radioactivity provided for a continual source of heat within the earth, and an age in billions of years, supporting Darwin's position.[9]
  4. ^ Jenkin was a polymath, and a friend of Kelvin's.
  5. ^ Blending inheritance was discarded in favour of Mendelian genetics early in the 20th century.
  6. ^ Huxley was known as "Darwin's Bulldog".

References[edit]

  1. ^ a b c d e f Largent, Mark A. (2009). "The So-Called Eclipse of Darwinism" (PDF). Descended from Darwin: Insights into the History of Evolutionary Studies, 1900–1970. American Philosophical Society.
  2. ^ (Huxley 1942, pp. 22–28)
  3. ^ (Bowler 2003, pp. 196, 224)
  4. ^ (Bowler 1983)
  5. ^ (Quammen 2006, pp. 216–223)
  6. ^ a b c (Mayr & Provine 1998, p. x)
  7. ^ (Quammen 2006, p. 205)
  8. ^ a b c d e f g (Bowler 1983, pp. 23–26)
  9. ^ (Bowler 1983, p. 3)
  10. ^ a b c (Bowler 2003, pp. 196–253)
  11. ^ a b (Larson 2004, pp. 105–129)
  12. ^ (Bowler 1983, p. 28)
  13. ^ (Endersby 2007, pp. 143,453)
  14. ^ (Larson 2004, p. 128)
  15. ^ (Bowler 2003, p. 197)
  16. ^ (Larson 2004, pp. 119–120)
  17. ^ (Quammen 2006, pp. 209–210)
  18. ^ (Endersby 2007, pp. 143–147,182)
  19. ^ (Bowler 1983, pp. 44–49)
  20. ^ (Secord 2001, pp. 424, 512)
  21. ^ (Bowler 1983, pp. 46, 49–50)
  22. ^ (Bowler 2003, pp. 203–206)
  23. ^ (Larson 2004, pp. 110–111)
  24. ^ (Bowler 1983, pp. 26–27, 44–45, 54–55)
  25. ^ (Bowler 2003, pp. 86–95)
  26. ^ (Darwin 1872, p. 108.)
  27. ^ a b c (Bowler 2003, pp. 236–244)
  28. ^ a b (Larson 2004, pp. 125–129)
  29. ^ Packard, Alpheus Spring; Putnam, Frederic Ward (1872). The Mammoth Cave and its Inhabitants. Salem Naturalists' Agency. p. 12. OCLC 04356215.
  30. ^ a b (Quammen 2006, pp. 217–219)
  31. ^ (Bowler 2003, pp. 239–240)
  32. ^ (Bowler 1983, pp. 41–42)
  33. ^ (Bowler 2003, pp. 253–255)
  34. ^ (Bowler 2003, pp. 243, 367)
  35. ^ a b (Quammen 2006, p. 221)
  36. ^ (Bowler 2003, p. 249)
  37. ^ (Bowler 2003, pp. 265–270)
  38. ^ (Larson 2004, pp. 127–129, 157–167)
  39. ^ (Endersby 2007, pp. 148–162)
  40. ^ (Endersby 2007, pp. 202–205)
  41. ^ Ramsey, Justin; Ramsey, Tara S. (August 2014). "Ecological studies of polyploidy in the 100 years following its discovery". Phil. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B. 5 (369): 20130352. doi:10.1098/rstb.2013.0352. PMC 4071525. PMID 24958925.
  42. ^ (Bowler 2003, pp. 269–272)
  43. ^ (Mayr & Provine 1998, pp. xi–xii)
  44. ^ (Mayr & Provine 1998, pp. 124–127, 296)
  45. ^ (Mayr & Provine 1998, pp. xii–xiii)
  46. ^ (Bowler 2003, p. 337)
  47. ^ (Ruse 1996)

Sources[edit]

  • Bowler, Peter J. (2003). Evolution:The History of an Idea. University of California Press. ISBN 0-520-23693-9.
  • Bowler, Peter J. (1983). The Eclipse of Darwinism: anti-Darwinian evolutionary theories in the decades around 1900. Johns Hopkins University Press. ISBN 978-0-8018-4391-4.
  • Darwin, Charles (1872). The Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, or the Preservation of Favored Races in the Struggle for Life (6th ed.). London: John Murray. ISBN 1-904633-78-1.
  • Endersby, Jim (2007). A Guinea Pig's History of Biology. Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-02713-8.
  • Huxley, Julian (1942). Evolution: the modern synthesis. London: Allen and Unwin.
  • Larson, Edward J. (2004). Evolution:The Remarkable History of Scientific Theory. Modern Library. ISBN 0-679-64288-9.
  • Mayr, Ernst; Provine, W. B., eds. (1998). The Evolutionary Synthesis: Perspectives on the Unification of Biology. Harvard University Press. ISBN 0-674-27225-0.
  • Quammen, David (2006). The Reluctant Mr. Darwin. Atlas Books. ISBN 0-393-05981-2.
  • Ruse, Michael (1996). Monad to Man: The Concept of Progress in Evolutionary Biology. Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-03248-4.
  • Secord, James A. (2001). Victorian Sensation: The Extraordinary Publication, Reception, and Secret Authorship of Vestiges of the Natural History of Creation. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-74410-0.